[scratching head…]
Well, I’m not sure where I should go from here. Suddenly, I’m precluded from debating the very core of Contention C. After putting on the back burner a thoroughly interesting study for what I believed to be a very interesting debate with a person whom I admire, I find that there is to be no debate, but rather that I am to answer a poll — does the notion of a social contract fit cozily within the person’s philosophy? That’s an approach I hadn’t considered in my libertarianism threads: don’t debate the implications of noncoercion, simply tell me whether noncoercion fits with libertarianism.
Take it to someone else? All right then, I will. 
Someone Else
Society and the collective unconscious will
I’m going to leave aside the name-dropping (Locke and Rousseau) and pretend it didn’t happen. I would have conceded willingly that the notion of society was not original to Xeno, or even to liberals. I don’t frankly know what relevance it would be if I could point to an historic figure and declare that here is the one who planted his flag on the shores of Societaria. I wouldn’t presume to argue its origins, but merely its pertinence to Contention C, i.e., whether a perceived social contract, as the basis of a moral imperative (or moral operative) adequately addresses the moral context of shared physical/spiritual realities.
The nature of society and the claim that its member elements are under contract is simply too much to let slide away unchallenged. I tried to wrap my brain around the explanation that society is not a metaphor but a vector, that it represents not only the collective will, but the unconscious collective will, that it serves as a weather vane pointing toward a consensus that is not mystical, but rather is as sure and plain as an orbiting moon pointing to gravity, or a mutation pointing to an organismic change. I honestly cannot squint and grunt my way to an understanding no matter how hard I try.
For one thing, a physicist can tell me about gravity, and a biologist can tell me about evolution. But who is going to tell me about the collective unconscious will? Who is going to perceive and mediate that which is not perceivable[sup]1[/sup]? I submit that such a philosophical mediation must be effected dictatorially, because bringing together a committee to decide the collective unconscious will walks right back into the same problem: what is the collective unconscious will of the committee?
I also cannot see how replacing “metaphor” with “vector” is any progress toward understanding, since vector itself is a metaphor in this case, unless you can show the vector equation of the collective unconscious will. In fact, what is offered to explain what society is and how it works leaves me more confused than when I thought it was merely a broad and arbitrary grouping[sup]2[/sup].
But let’s be gracious and leave even all that aside. Let’s grant Xeno that he has an understanding of society that is difficult to mediate. I can empathize. I run into the same problem when I must describe the spirit, though I admit that I must resort to metaphors since the spirit cannot be perceived by the senses. Let’s grant, if only for the sake of argument, that society is the collective unconscious will, and that there is a sure way to relate that will to a governing entity. When we allow that, we run headlong into these:
No no no no no. What it delivers is the minimum freedom to individuals, because it (presumably) calculates the lowest common denominator of unconscious will. That is, it enforces the intersection upon the union. The way to deliver the maximum freedom to individuals is to recognize, not their shared will, but their individual autonomous will. Allow Smith, Jones, and Brown each to exercise his own will as he sees it, so long as none imposes his will upon any other. Let Smith be free from the imposition of Jones and Brown; let Jones be free from the imposition of Smith and Brown; and let Brown be free from the impostion of Smith and Jones. Voila. Maximum freedom to individuals.
If not maximum freedom, then what maximum does modern liberalism deliver? It delivers the maximum homogeny. Because it takes its marching orders from the collective unconscious will, it is like a manifold of rivers feeding into a central sea. Modern liberalism is morphing into centrism right before our eyes. Just as water seeks its own level, and does so as expeditiously as possible, so does liberalism seek to homogenize society because the problematic divining of the collective unconscious will is eventually replaced by the simple mediation of a single unconscious will that is shared by all. Thus, any arbitrary element of the society may express the society’s will, since the will of the elements is all the same. I am not arguing a slippery slope of implication, but rather a direction of intention. Society itself might not have a collective intention, as Xeno pointed out, but those who govern it do.
That is all well and good so long as your liberty from economic oppression does not constitute my subjection to it, and so long as your freedom of action does not trump mine. Otherwise, you leave Smith free to take Jones’s money to help Brown, or you leave Mr. Smith and Ms. Jones free to make love, but not Mr. Smith and Mr. Brown. Unfortunately, that is exactly what happens with liberalism. “Economic oppression” translates into “economic inequality”. Thus, if Jones has $1,000, Smith has $500, and Brown has $100, liberalism discerns an oppression and seeks to redistribute the wealth, ideally leaving Jones, Smith, and Brown each with $400. I submit that neither Jones nor Smith were free from economic oppression in the process of redistribution, neither was either “free to act” by refusing to give his money over to you. Oh. Where did the other $400 go? It went to build the building, pay the staff, buy the supplies, and provide the salaries of the people who did the redistributing.
Let’s assign the nominatives here, and not leave them dangling to interpretation. It requires a concern by an employer for worker safety, leaving the worker every sort of way to wiggle out of any responsibility of his own. It does not merely require that the employer honestly represent any safety hazards, as libertarianism does, but that the worker may assume no hazards await him. Every one of these liberal homogeny projects necessarily generates an oversight entity, such as OSHA, and a mitigation entity, such as Workers Compensation, so that the collective unconscious will can be enforced. The concern for environmental protection is assigned, not to the owners of the property, but to the governors of it. It presumes that the interest of the governors is arbitrarily more benign than the interest of the land owners. And it assigns concern for fair trade, not to the people who trade with one another, but to their governors. Thus, you can buy a Mexican cigar, but not a Cuban one.
Unfortunately, that is as true as it can be. Jones and Smith decide that all three ought to wear seatbelts. Their collective unconscious will carries because they are a majority over Brown, rendering Brown’s participation futile and irrelevant. Brown must now wear a seat belt despite the excrutiating pain he experiences as the belt presses against his abdominal hernia. He is not allowed to manage his own safety in some other way. Why not? Because the collective unconscious will has determined that seatbelts are the best safety management. There is no need for entrepreneural advancement because the solution has been found. The oversight and mitigation entities that enforce the wearing of seatbelts have no incentive even to allow alternatives, because their mission is clearly defined: make people wear seatbelts and redistribute the wealth to compensate those who get hurt anyway. If something besides seatbelts were shown to be an improvement in safety, suddenly the seatbelt experts and mitigators would be unnecessary. That is why a bureaucracy that is not market-based never goes away. Even bureaucrats understand what is in their self-interest, and unlike Mr. Brown, they have the power and authority to implement theirs.
I don’t deny that its intentions are based on noble ideals. On its surface, modern liberalism merely seeks to level the playing field in order to provide equal opportunity for all. Unfortunately, there are already people standing on that field, and when you grade it out from under them, you are diminishing their opportunities. Like so many noble intentions, the implementation often produces unanticipated side-effects. Though the intention is maximum freedom for every individual, the effect is homogeny, leaving no one free at all.
The social contract
Libertarianism recognizes certain unary contracts, that is, contracts that do not require the consent of all its parties. The contract between a parent and a child is one such. The child had no part in his existence that involved his own will; rather, he was the product of his parents’ will. Moreover, the child is incapable of giving meaningful consent, and thus it falls to his parents to execute the contract unilaterally. But even a unary contract must have at least one consentor, and all parties who do not consent must be unable to give meaningful consent.
The alleged social contract, like society, is an arbitrary construct conceived and offered for the sole purpose of legitimizing tyranny. That is why libertarians find the notion of a social contract so deplorable. When we protest that we did not sign and do not consent, we encounter the argument that our continued presence within the boundaries defined by the contract’s enforcer constitutes our consent. Thus, we are born into this foggy contract and can relieve ourselves of our obligation to it only by abandoning whatever property we have improved with our toil, sweat, and capital. It is not a matter that our consent is not meaningful, but that our meaningful consent was extruded from us in our sleep. The cat stole our breath, and we find ourselves in the Twilight Zone.
Not only are we living in a weird dream imposed upon us by those with the most political clout, but we find that, absent enough clout of our own, the terms of our contract can and do change. Daily. And if we don’t like it, we can go live out in the ocean. We can vote and vote and vote, but until the collective unconscious will intersects exactly with our own conscious will, we cannot escape the obligations to which we never consented. And what exactly are those obligations? What are the terms of the contract? They are so many that volumes and volumes in whole libraries house their contents. We must obtain the equivalent of a masters degree before we can even understand them, let alone consent to them.
I suppose what is most remarkable to me is that the liberal philosophy lays claim to an intention to implement fairness, while holding that the social contract, the very basis of its justification, is fair. I suppose it is no wonder that if a contract that can bind parties capable of giving meaningful consent, but whose consent is presumed from their mere existence, is seen as fair, then the redistribution of resources, planned by the examination of an unperceivable unconscious will — and against the express conscious will of those who are pillaged — is seen as maxium freedom.
Xeno
Tell me where I am. Tell me whether I’m wasting your time and mine here.
[/quote]
[sup]1[/sup] unconscious: “The division of the mind in psychoanalytic theory containing elements of psychic makeup, such as memories or repressed desires, that are not subject to conscious perception or control but that often affect conscious thoughts and behavior.” — The American Heritage® Dictionary of the English Language, Fourth Edition, Copyright © 2000 by Houghton Mifflin Company.
[sup]2[/sup] society: “A group of humans broadly distinguished from other groups by mutual interests, participation in characteristic relationships, shared institutions, and a common culture.” — Ibid.