I’m getting increasingly frustrated by the confusion going around regarding the “precautionary principle”. People seem to think it means being cautious, or in many cases super cautious, to the point of ridiculous action or inaction.
It means nothing of the sort.
Let me start with the birth of the “precautionary principle” (I’ll call it PP for short), which comes from the UN Rio Declaration on the Environment (1992). Here’s their original formulation:
“In order to protect the environment, the precautionary approach shall be widely applied by States according to their capability. Where there are threats of serious or irreversible damage, lack of full scientific certainty shall not be used as a reason for postponing cost-effective measures to prevent environmental degradation.”
This is an excellent statement of the PP, as it distinguishes it from such things as wearing condoms, denying bank loans, approving the Kyoto Protocol, invading Afghanistan, or using seat belts.
The three key parts of the PP (emphasis mine) are:
-
A threat of serious or irreversible damage.
-
A lack of full scientific certainty (in other words, the existence of partial but not conclusive scientific evidence).
-
The availability of cost-effective measures.
Here are some examples of how these key parts of the PP work out in practice.
We have full scientific certainty that condoms and seat belts save lives. Thus, using them is not an example of the PP, it is simply acting reasonably on principles about which we are scientifically certain.
There are no scientific principles or evidence that we can apply to the question of invading Afghanistan, so we cannot apply the PP there either.
Bank loans are neither serious nor irreversible, nor is there partial scientific understanding of them, so they don’t qualify for the PP.
Finally, the Kyoto Protocol is so far from being cost-effective as to be laughable. The PP can be thought of as a kind of insurance policy. No one would pay $200,000 for an insurance policy if the payoff in case of an accident were only $20, yet this is the kind of ratio of cost to payoff that the Kyoto Protocol involves.
On the other side of the equation, a good example of when we might use the PP involves local extinction. We have fairly good scientific understanding that removing a top predator from a local ecosystem badly screws things up. If you kill the mountain lions, the deer population skyrockets, then the plants are overgrazed, then the ground erodes, insect populations are unbalanced, and so on down the line.
So, if we are looking at a novel ecosystem that has not been scientifically studied, we do not have full scientific certainty that removing the top predator will actually cause serious or irreversible damage to the ecosystem. However, if there is a cost-effective method to avoid removing the top predator, the PP says that we should do so. It fulfils the three requirements of the PP – there is a threat of serious damage, we have partial scientific certainty, and a cost-effective solution exists, so we should act.
I see the PP being invoked in all kinds of situations where it has no application at all, to justify an approach which is so cautious as to be absolutely paralyzing. Dear friends, caution is good in its place … but caution is not any part of the precautionary principle.
w.